Collapse of the wave function. Sounds intense, in’t? What does it mean? That’s the topic of this post. When we discussed the second and third postulates of quantum mechanics, we saw that, for a given physical observable , we can only measure an eigenvalue
of the operator
associated with
. We also saw with the fourth postulate that the probability to measure this eigenvalue is given by the probability to find the quantum system in the eigenstate
of
associated with
. The fifth postulate determines what happens to the system after we have measured
.
Postulate V: For a system in state
, immediately after measuring observable
, the system is in
, where
is the state associated with eigenvalue
, which resulted from the measurement.
In other words, the fact of measuring “projects” the system onto state
. Mathematically, the projection can be represented using the projector operator
,
(1)
This is sometimes referred to as the collapse of the wave function because the measurement causes the system to be in one particular eigenstate of the measurement operator even if it was previously in a superposition state. Any information about the state of the system before the measurement is lost, except for the fact that the system had a non-zero probability of being in state . For example, if the system is initially in the superposition state
, we know from the forth postulate that the probability of measuring the angular momentum along the
axis to be
is
. If we do measure the angular momentum along the
axis to be
despite the low probability, the fifth postulate tells us that the system will then be in the eigenstate of
associated with the eigenvalue
, i.e.,
. The system is now entirely in state
and the information that the system previously had a large probability of being in state
is lost. In the case where the system is in a state which happens to be an eigenstate of the operator we are trying to measure (here,
), then the measurement can only result in the eigenvalue associated with the eigenstate. Then, the measurement leaves the state unchanged, and the state collapses onto itself.
The postulates of quantum mechanics were laid down a century ago. Should modern physicists sit down and rethink the way the postulates are phrased, this one is probably the one where they would have to scratch their head the most. A century ago, measurements on quantum systems were performed very differently than what can be achieved today. For example, in a Stern-Gerlach experiment, spins in and
were physically separated in space thanks to a strong magnetic field and detected using a metallic plate stopping the particles and revealing their trajectory. Here, measuring the state of the system (
or
) does disturb the system. To the contrary, modern experimental techniques have offered evidence that it is possible to detect quantum mechanical properties in much more delicate way, or in more technical terms, in a non-destructive way, meaning that it does not collapse the state of the system.
Any measurement on a quantum mechanical system requires an interface between the microscopic quantum mechanical system and the macroscopic world so that we, humans, can read it out. That’s where the difference lies between experiments in the first half of the twentieth century and what can be done now. While a Stern-Gerlach experiment brutally crushes the measured atoms on a metal plates, modern methods such as quantum sensing use quantum mechanical systems as an intermediate to measure properties of another quantum mechanical systems indirectly, minimizing the perturbation experienced by the system of interest.
In modern standard NMR experiments, this postulate has limited practical implications. Yet, it is still provides insights for some experiments. Take the liquid-state NMR spectrum of a 13C spin J-coupled to a 1H spin (for example in 13C-formate). Anyone with basic NMR knowledge knows what this spectrum looks like: it’s a doublet. In other words, two peaks separated by the J coupling value. This splitting comes from the fact that each 13C spin has its resonance shifted up or down, depending on the state of the 1H spin coupled to it. In usual conditions, an individual 1H spin does not need to be either in the or
states but can be in any superposition of those, with a slight preference for the
state. One could then expect that the 13C spins experiences a continuous distribution of field produced by the 1H neighbor. Yet, they don’t: they see the 1H spin either in the
or
state. This can be seen as the collapse of the 1H spin state due to the interaction with the 13C spin that we are observing.
Do we need to measure the 13C spectrum for the 1H spin wave function to collapse? No. The 13C spins always experiences the 1H spin being either in the or
state. So is it really the fact of performing the measurement, as we scientists perform in the lab, that cause the wave function to collapse? As far as I, the author of this post, know, this is still a question under debate in Physics and Epistemology of Science and it is certainly past the borders of my own knowledge!
In this post, we discussed an interesting and troubling notion in quantum mechanics: the consequence of performing a measurement. I attempted explaining how it can be understood from the NMR point of view. In the next post, we come back to more concrete grounds as we discuss how quantum mechanical systems evolve in time, according the time-dependent Schrödinger equation.